Thing or Things




The word thing is one of the most commonly used words in everyday speech. It is both concrete yet ambiguous, indicating what is sure but not clear. The word thing carries with it all the weight of existence without a conviction about specifics. ‘Thing’ is usually taken to derive from the Germanic ‘ding,’ or the old English ‘þing,’ which means gathering or assembly. Interests come together in a thing: a thing is composed of attachments—the meaning of a thing is caught in its relations.



But ‘thing’ has a charged philosophical history.

    That a thing bears many qualities has been said by both Plato and Aristotle. Later on, it is expressed in other words and concepts, however the meaning is generally the same even when the philosophical positions are different.

    In Critique of Pure Reason, Immanuel Kant claims that philosophy has no hope of discussing the way things are in themselves—reality independent from perception—since our thinking and conceptual capacities are limited. This rift divides noumena from phenomena, or the thing-in-itself from its appearance within our conscious experience. Kant’s thing-in-itself is the thing as it truly is, understood apart from our subjective modes of representation.

    In Phenomenology of Spirit, G.W.F. Hegel rejects the Kantian division between thing and appearance. For Hegel, a thing is the result of a certain conceptual scheme—the thing is what appears as a thing given our methodological approach, or put differently: it is the scientific phenomenon inside of our scientific paradigm. Consequently, the thing is already conditioned by our understanding and is not an abstracted thing-in-itself. For Hegel, human representations are not ultimately determined, but rather are continually molded and reshaped in something that resembles a historical process. Hegel demonstrates that even seemingly obvious and solid things change constantly and are relative to us.

    A different way of rejecting the thing-in-itself is found in the phenomenology of Edmund Husserl. For Husserl, the reality of a thing is to appear as a phenomenon for human consciousness—any existence of things outside of consciousness is secondary. Phenomenology opposes all forms of naturalism; any explanatory theory about things must give way to a simple treatment of things as they show themselves. In order to overcome scientific naturalism, Husserl restricts things to their surface effects. The project of phenomenology is an attempt to grasp the thing, by means of reduction. Husserl’s contributions to philosophy reveal the ongoing tension between a thing and its qualities—what we encounter in perception is neither the thing nor its raw qualities; perception is always already an interpretation.

    In some ways, the thing is Martin Heidegger’s most important idea, one that encapsulates all the insights of his career. Culminating in his 1927 masterpiece Being and Time, Heidegger revolutionized our concept of things. For Heidegger, things are events, not perceptual or physical occurrences. They are a how, not a what—in other words, they cannot be reduced to a list of traits and qualities. Heidegger guides us through two dramatic ideas in rethinking things: the first is the concept of tool-analysis, where things withdraw from presence into their silent function, and the second is the concept of the fourfold, where things become quadruple mirrors, with each pole reflecting all the others. What Heidegger gives to philosophy is a model of things impenetrable to human intellect and equally opaque in everyday human use.

    For Sigmund Freud, the thing is the lost object, what’s absent in the subject. Jacques Lacan translates Freud’s neuronal understanding of the thing into a semiotic one: the thing is the signifier cut off from the chain of signification.

    Maurice Merleau-Ponty brings up how the perceiving subject comes to distinguish itself from the outside world, attempting to explain why we don’t think of ourselves as things.

    Karl Marx is one of the first to notice that things can define society, even more than people; capitalist production is founded on the creation of commodities out of things.

    Paul-Michel Foucault demonstrates in The Order of Things that the history of the thing—history beyond the subject—was central to the first understandings of “history,” meaning the development of history as an object of study in the 19th century. 

    Anthropologists like Bruno Latour and Arjun Appadurai have constructed entire theories of society and history around thing-ness as an attempt to understand the world not as a product of human subjectivity. 

    Other extensions of thing into critical theory include Bill Brown’s proposal of thing theory as an analogue to narrative theory or cultural theory—thing theory is intended to explain how inanimate objects constitute human subjects.

But a thing is not just for humans—a thing is for many other things as well, both material and immaterial.



    In metaphysics, object-oriented ontology is a 21st century Heidegger-influenced school of thought that rejects the privileging of subject-object relations over object-object relations. Founded by Graham Harman, the object-oriented position makes distinct claims about the nature and equality of relations: all relations, including object-object relations, distort objects in the same basic manner and exist on an equal footing with one another.


   
‘Thing’ offers itself as an alternative to ‘object,’ dissolving the dichotomy between subject and object. Because of its ambiguity, the word thing carries a notion of the unmediated, a world without a code, beyond the perceiving subject and the representations that are created by the subject around the thing.

Thing means anything which meets two criteria:
    1. irreducible downward to its components
    2. irreducible upward to its effects

A thing is any unified entity irreducible to its components or to its effects on the surrounding environment.



    How does one retain things—neither too closed on themselves, nor too transient? The question of the thing is not a question of how we know the thing, but a question of what things are. What a thing is cannot be reduced to our access to things—access which is highly limited. Things withdraw, not just from human access, but from each other as well.

A thing is more than its appearance, more than its usefulness, and more than its physical body.

    There is always more to a thing than anything we can see or say about it. Things lie simultaneously at hand and somewhere outside the theoretical field, beyond a certain limit, as a recognizable yet illegible remainder that is unspecifiable. The ambiguity of things and the ambiguity in things: to be a thing is to be riddled in contradiction.

    The significance of one thing to another differs depending on the perspectives of both. When one thing characterizes another, the first grasps the second in abstract, enough for the one to make some sense of the other, given its own internal properties. A thing’s means of making sense of another is not universal and cannot be explained away through natural law, scientific truth, or even its own perspective. To understand how a thing operates on its surroundings, or they on it, is not the same as understanding how the thing itself understands those operations.

    There is an absolute difference between perception and what is being perceived; any reality can be endlessly explored and viewed from numberless perspectives without ever being exhausted by the sum of these perspectives. Reality is always different from our perceptions of it; any form of perception will never be the exact equivalent of what it perceives.

Put differently: all things translate one another and the things that are translated are irreducible to their translations.

    Perhaps the most that can be said with confidence about a thing is that it eludes capture by any concept. Concepts can never provide a clear view of things in themselves, but can gesture toward them.



    Knowledge is less like seeing and more like interpretation, since things can never be directly or completely present to us. The point of knowledge is not to experience the unknowable uniqueness of a thing, but to obtain some sort of partial grasp of the features of a thing that is already in our midst.

    Everyone searches for an identity, for a single meaning, and a common sense to things. Therefore, everyone fixes the meaning of things, of their life, of the lives of others, or of their acts at a specific sign. Meaning is never given, but obtained through the elimination and relativism of other possible meanings. In truth, this meaning—neither completely existential nor completely semiotic—is simply the possibility of passing from one thing to another.

A thing among things.








Reading Things




Appadurai, Arjun. The Social Life of Things: Commodities in Cultural Perspective. Cambridge University Press, 1988.

Austin, J., et al. How to Do Things with Words. 2nd ed., Harvard University Press, 1975.

Badiou, Alain, and Louise Burchill. Deleuze: The Clamor of Being. First edition, University of Minnesota Press, 1999.

Bennett, Jane. Vibrant Matter: A Political Ecology of Things. Unknown, Duke University Press Books, 2010.

Bogost, Ian. What It’s Like to Be a Thing. 1st ed., Univ Of Minnesota Press, 2012.

Braver, Lee. A Thing of This World: A History of Continental Anti-Realism. 1st ed., Northwestern University Press, 2007.

Brown, Bill. Other Things. Illustrated, University of Chicago Press, 2019.

---. Things. University of Chicago Press, 2004.

Bryant, Levi. Difference and Givenness: Deleuze’s Transcendental Empiricism and the Ontology of Immanence. 1st ed., Northwestern University Press, 2008.

---. The Democracy of Objects. Open Humanities Press, 2011.

Bryant, Harman, and Nick Srnicek. The Speculative Turn: Continental Materialism and Realism. First Edition, re.press, 2011.

Cogburn, Jon. Garcian Meditations: The Dialectics of Persistence in Form and Object. 1st ed., Edinburgh University Press, 2017.

Colletti, Lucio, and Lawrence Garner. Marxism and Hegel. First Edition, New Left Books, 1973.

DeLanda, Manuel. Assemblage Theory. 1st ed., Edinburgh University Press, 2016.

---. Intensive Science and Virtual Philosophy. Zaltbommel-Netherlands, Netherlands, Van Haren Publishing, 2013.

DeLanda, M., & Harman, G. The Rise of Realism (1st ed.). Polity, 2017.

Deleuze, Gilles, and Paul Patton. Difference and Repetition. Revised ed., Columbia University Press, 1995.

Derrida, Jacques, and Alan Bass. Margins of Philosophy. Reprint, University of Chicago Press, 1985.

Figal, Günter, and Jerome Veith. Aesthetics as Phenomenology: The Appearance of Things. Indiana University Press, 2015.

Foucault, Michel. The Order of Things: An Archaeology of the Human Sciences. Illustrated, Vintage, 1994.

Garcia, Tristan, et al. Form and Object: A Treatise on Things. 1st ed., Edinburgh University Press, 2014.

Hacking, Ian. The Social Construction of What? Revised, Harvard University Press, 2000.

Hallward, Peter. Badiou: A Subject To Truth. First edition, Univ Of Minnesota Press, 2003.

Harman, Graham. Bells and Whistles: More Speculative Realism. Zero Books, 2013.

---. Guerrilla Metaphysics: Phenomenology and the Carpentry of Things. 1st US-1st Printing, Open Court, 2005.

---. Immaterialism: Objects and Social Theory. 1st ed., Polity, 2016.

---. Object-Oriented Ontology: A New Theory of Everything. Illustrated, Pelican, 2018.

---. The Quadruple Object. Reprint, Zero Books, 2011.

---. Tool-Being: Heidegger and the Metaphysics of Objects (First Edition). Open Court, 2002.

---. Towards Speculative Realism: Essays and Lectures. Reprint, Zero Books, 2010.

Hegel, G., Glenn Gray, et al. On Art, Religion, and the History of Philosophy: Introductory Lectures. Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1997.

Hegel, G., A. Miller, et al. Phenomenology of Spirit. Revised ed., Oxford University Press, 1977.

Hegel, Georg. Science of Logic. CreateSpace Independent Publishing Platform, 2017.

Heidegger, Martin, Metcalf, et al. Basic Concepts of Aristotelian Philosophy. Amsterdam-Netherlands, Netherlands, Amsterdam University Press, 2009.

Heidegger, Martin. Being and Time. Reprint, Harper Perennial Modern Classics, 2008.

---. Phenomenological Interpretation of Kant’s Critique of Pure Reason. N, Indiana University Press, 1997.

---. Phenomenological Interpretations of Aristotle: Initiation into Phenomenological Research. Indiana University Press, 2008.

Heidegger, Martin, W. Barton, et al. What Is a Thing? First Edition, Henry Regnery Company, 1967.

Heidegger, Martin, and Albert Hofstadter. The Basic Problems of Phenomenology, Revised Edition. Revised, Indiana University Press, 1988.

Heidegger, Martin, and Richard Taft. Kant and the Problem of Metaphysics. Fifth Edition, Enlarged, Indiana University Press, 1997.

Husserl, Edmund. Ideas: General Introduction to Pure Phenomenology. Martino Fine Books, 2017.

Husserl, Edmund, and Dorion Cairns. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. Martinus Nijhoff Pub., 1977.

Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Judgement. Free Press, 2008.

---. Critique of Pure Reason: Unified Edition (with All Variants from the 1781 and 1787 Editions). 1st Edition, Hackett Publishing Company, Inc., 1996.

Latour, Bruno. Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. 1st ed., Oxford University Press, 2007.

Levinas, E. Totality and Infinity: An Essay on Exteriority. Springer Fachmedien, 1980.

Lingis, A. The Imperative (Studies in Continental Thought). Indiana University Press, 1998.

Meillassoux, Quentin, et al. After Finitude: An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. Continuum, 2010.

Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Donald Landes, et al. Phenomenology of Perception. 1st ed., Routledge, 2013.

Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, Claude Lefort, et al. The Visible and the Invisible. 1st ed., Northwestern University Press, 1968.

Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, and Patricia Allen Dreyfus. Sense and Non-Sense. Northwestern University Press, 1992.

Scott, Charles. The Lives of Things. Indiana University Press, 2002.

Whitehead, Alfred North. Modes of Thought. The Free Press, 1968.

---. Process and Reality (Gifford Lectures Delivered in the University of Edinburgh During the Session 1927-28). 2nd ed., Free Press, 1979.